Phenomenology Summer School 2015 Reminder

CA’ FOSCARI UNIVERSITY VENICE

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY AND CULTURAL HERITAGE

SUMMER SCHOOL OF PHENOMENOLOGY AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY:

PHENOMENOLOGY AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

VENICE, JULY 07-10, 2015

The Department of Philosophy and Cultural Heritage of Ca’ Foscari University Venice (Italy) is pleased to host the third edition of the SSPPP (Summer School of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy).

The Summer School will take place on 07-10.7.2015.

Language: English

Seminars will be led by:

Patrice Canivez (University of Lille)

Daniele de Santis (Seattle University)

Nicolas de Warren (Husserl Archives at KU Leuven)

Matteo Giannasi (Ca’ Foscari University Venice)

Burt Hopkins (Seattle University)

Edouard Jolly (University of Leuven)

Claudio Majolino (University of Lille)

Darian Meacham (University of the West of England)

Gianluigi Paltrinieri (Ca’ Foscari University Venice)

Emiliano Trizio (Seattle University)

The number of attendants being limited, a selection will take place among aspirant students. Applicants are kindly requested to send a CV and a sample of writing (optional) to phenomenologysummerschool@gmail.com

Deadline for application submission: May 23, 2015 (Late applicants will be shortlisted and contacted on the basis of the number of attendants).

Notification of acceptance: May 24, 2015

The event is organized and sponsored by the Department of Philosophy and Cultural Heritage of Ca’ Foscari University Venice.

Participation fee: 100 euro (50 for Ca’ Foscari students).

PHENOMENOLOGY AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

The relation between phenomenology and political philosophy can be ranged among the least investigated themes of the phenomenological tradition, to the point that it is legitimate to claim that the potentialities of this field of study have barely begun to be explored. The reasons for this widespread and persistent forgetfulness are often deemed to be rooted in the history of phenomenology itself, which has been marked by the predominance of foundational issues revolving chiefly around the theory of knowledge (Husserl) and the problem of being (Heidegger). Indeed, although a number of prominent authors belonging to this tradition have produced a considerable amount of work on social and political philosophy, and have, for better or worse, actively participated to the political life of their time, it is not always clear to what extent their contribution to the reflection on social and political issues stems from their phenomenological outlook, rather than being just juxtaposed to it. This is true both of Heidegger’s tragic proximity to Nazism, and of the Marxist creed predominant among some post-war phenomenologists. Subsequently, the so-called end of ideologies and the predominance of an apolitical academic style of philosophy have widened the gulf between a highly technical discipline such as phenomenology and the reflection on the surrounding political and social context. Ethical and broadly existential issues have thus replaced the strongly political and practical concerns of authors such as Jean-Paul Sartre in France, Enzo Paci in Italy or Ludwig Landgrebe in Germany, to name a few. Yet, more recently, a number of works has renewed the interest in the way in which phenomenology can give a valuable contribution to issues fundamental to political philosophy: intersubjectivity, life-world, the constitution of social and cultural objects, the concepts of state and democracy, power, authority and technology, the reflection on the meaning of history and on the philosophical idea of Europe. Consequently, it has now become possible to highlight an underlying political motive that permeates 20th Century phenomenology since its inception (from Husserl to Patočka, from Heidegger to Arendt), reassess the judgments of its most prominent critiques (from the Frankfurt School to various post-modern appraisals) and, further, to pave the way to new original phenomenological investigations in this area, as well as to a confrontation with other major trends in political philosophy.

No previous background in phenomenology is required. On the final day of the seminar, advanced students will be encouraged to give a personal contribution to the School’s activities.

Program

Tuesday, July 07

Morning

9:00-9:45 Registration

9:45-10:00 Welcome

10:00-13:00 Darian Meacham (UWE, Bristol/BrisSynBio)

European Institutions? The European Crisis and The Crisis of the European Sciences

13:00-15:00 Lunch break

Afternoon

15:00-16:30 Emiliano Trizio (Seattle University)

On Klaus Held’s Phenomenology of the Political World

16:30-17:00 Coffee break

17:00-18:30 Matteo Giannasi (Ca’ Foscari University Venice)

Humanity without Human Nature. The Significance of Husserl’s Antinaturalistic Critique of Relativism

Morning

10:00-13:00 Claudio Majolino (University of Lille)

The Unhuman Condition and Beyond. Husserl and the Constitution of Practical Manifolds

13:00-15:00 Lunch break

Afternoon

15:00-16:30 Daniele de Santis (Seattle University)

Phenomenology of Life and Capital. On Michel Henry’s Interpretation of Marx

16:30-17:00 Coffee break

17:00-18:30 Burt Hopkins (Seattle University)

The Politics of Consciousness: On the Eidetic Structure of Political Knowledge

Thursday, July 09

Morning

10:00-13:00 Nicolas de Warren (Husserl Archives at KU Leuven)

Band of Brothers: Fraternity and Terror in Sartre’s Social Ontology

13:00-15:00 Lunch break

Afternoon

15:00-16:30 Gian Luigi Paltrinieri (Ca’ Foscari University Venice)

Earth, Soil, Territory. How could Martin Heidegger, Interpreter of Phenomenology, become a Nazi?

16:30-17:00 Coffee break

17:00-18:30 Edouard Jolly (Husserl Archives at KU Leuven)

What is Politics ? Arendt’s Political Phenomenology Between History of Violence and Kriegsfrage

Friday, July 10

Morning

10:00-13:00 Student Presentations

Moderator: Patrice Canivez (University of Lille)

13:00-15:00 Lunch break

Afternoon

15:00-18:00 Student Presentations

Moderator: Patrice Canivez (University of Lille)

18:00-18:10 Conclusion and greetings

ABSTRACTS OF THE SEMINARS

Daniele De Santis (Seattle University)

Phenomenology of Life and Capital. On Michel Henry’s Interpretation of Marx

In his 1976 two volume book on Marx (Marx I: Une Philosophie de la realité; II: Une philosophie de l’économie; English trans. by K. McLaughlin, Marx. A Philosophy of Human Reality (1983)), the French phenomenologist Michel Henry proposes a twofold line of interpretation. On the one hand, Henry attempts at a phenomenological interpretation of Marx’s philosophy and writings in the light of his phenomenology of life and immanence; one the other, he aims at presenting Marx himself as a phenomenologist. According to this double pattern, the present seminar will strive to achieve the following three main goals: (i) to flesh out the main traits of Henry’s interpretation of Marx’s deeply ontological understanding of “being” as “praxis” (he speaks indeed of Marx’s “radical ontology of praxis”) and thereby what Henry holds to be Marx’s own “new sense of the concept of subjectivity” (“The concept of being is subjectivity. Subjectivity is what permits beings to be”) able to accomplish, as Henry emphatically puts it, a “radical reverse” of “Western philosophy”; (ii) to analyze Henry’s own concept of subjectivity as a “monadic structure of being” and corporeal life construed of as “a multiplicity of possible activities and intentionalities” (as Henry explains: “It presents itself to us phenomenologically as a totality to the extent that it carries within itself, in the form of potentialities, a multiplicity of possible activities and intentionalities”); (iii) to explain what Henry considers both Marx’s “eidetic analysis” of the relationships between “capital”, “labor” and “living subjectivity” as the “power of creation and growth” as well as his idea of a “transcendental genesis” or “origin” of economic reality (as Henry points out: “The origin of economic reality is its ground. The transcendental genesis of the economic has the following radical meaning: reality, which is in itself is noneconomic, is the reality of economic reality”).

Nicolas de Warren (Husserl Archives at KU Leuven)

Band of Brothers: Fraternity and Terror in Sartre’s Social Ontology

This lecture introduces students to key elements of Sartre’s social ontology in Critique of Dialectical Reason. Along with a presentation of Sartre’s notions of “the third,” “praxis and practico-inert,” “mediated reciprocity” and the operative phenomenological vocabulary of “transcendence and immanence,” this lecture will center on Sartre’s original analysis of the function of pledging for the constitution of permanent social groups. In so doing, this lecture seeks to understand the meaning of Sartre’s insight that man is “violent—throughout History right up to the present day […]—to the anti-human (that is to say, to any other man) and to his Brother in so far as he has the permanent possibility of becoming anti-human himself.”

Matteo Giannasi (Ca’ Foscari University Venice)

Humanity without Human Nature. The Significance of Husserl’s Antinaturalistic Critique of Relativism

Husserl’s phenomenological project is characterized by strong ethical motivations and implications. Although his early criticism of psychologism in Logical Investigations appears as a merely technical refutation of epistemological mistakes, it soon revealed its true significance against the background of Husserl’s philosophical and scientific project, aiming to heal contemporary life from what Husserl considered as a dangerous and pervasive cultural disease: relativism, a pathology leading modern humanity to a social and political breakdown, and indirectly responsible for the outbreak of global conflicts and even wars. Phenomenology can be viewed as a titanic effort to revive the modern project of fully actualizing the human potential, by asserting the centrality and universal validity of human reason, against the spreading of relativistic tendencies in contemporary society and philosophy. The very concept of relativism attains philosophical centrality in his analyses and descriptions. Although the concept of humanity (Menschlichkeit, Humanität) plays a central role in his philosophical project, Husserl’s diagnose of the disease of contemporary science and culture identifies its source in their naturalism, a tendency he holds responsible for all modern forms of logical, but also social, ethical, and political relativism. Husserl’s antirelativistic insistence on the centrality of a properly human life is therefore completely alternative to ancient or modern forms of reference to a purported common human nature, and pivots, rather, on axiological and ethical concepts, such as validity, correctness, responsibility and conscience. Can such a form of relativism still play a role in contemporary ethical and political debates? Is Husserl’s radically anti-naturalistic stance still a respectable position in the 21st century? What are its limits and what can we learn from it? The seminar focuses on Husserl’s lectures on ethics and theory of value, as well as on later developments of his philosophical position in Formal and Transcendental Logic and in the Krisis.

Burt Hopkins (Seattle University)

The Politics of Consciousness: On the Eidetic Structure of Political Knowledge

Husserl’s 1919 letter to Arnold Metzger, in the aftermath of the Great War, gently admonishes its recipient about the impossibility of living a philosophical life committed at once to “the studies of human realities and their philosophical clarification and guidance” and to the theoretical work of pure scientific philosophy. Husserl cites no less an authority on this impossibility than his “daimon,” which warned him, “I am not called to lead humanity in striving for a happy life.” Significantly, however, Husserl relates to Metzger that he does “not consider truth and science the highest values,” because “‘Intellect is the servant of the will’.” Given this, Husserl’s “apportionment of [the theoretical and practical] functions,” it is left to those phenomenologists who follow him to address the phenomenological problem of politics. My lecture will do just this by providing an eidetic analysis of the structure of political knowledge. The methodological necessity in phenomenology’s descriptive cognition for a guiding clue will be supplied in my analysis by Plato’s investigation of the cosmic appearance of political episteme in the Statesman. In line with this, the problem of the Not-Being of the more and the less will be confronted phenomenologically. This confrontation will take place both in terms of the manifestation of the more and the less in the most basic mathematical relations and its necessary epistemic transformation in political episteme. The theme of my lecture will therefore be the transformation of the mathematical relation of the more and less into ontological excess and deficiency, a transformation that has its phenomenological basis in the techne of how to generate political being in accordance with due measure—that is, in political knowledge.

Edouard Jolly (Husserl Archives at KU Leuven)

What is Politics? Arendt’s Political Phenomenology Between History of Violence and Kriegsfrage

A human world providing freedom to act and to think: this is the political answer to the question “what do we have to do?” chosen by Arendt in her essays united under the title Was ist Politik?, which were written between 1956 and 1959. The purpose of my lecture will be to examine the Arendtian conception of politics, as it relates to political phenomena such as violence and war. The general question I will ask is the following: in order to produce an effective political phenomenology, in which manner is it essential to think with and against history and political conceptions, in addition to philosophy? We will see that Arendt is a good example in political phenomenology, especially because of her question about the possibility of losing the world (Weltlosigkeit) and its relation with freedom. We will understand the problem of unworldliness through history.

Claudio Majolino (University of Lille)

The Unhuman Condition and Beyond. Husserl and the Constitution of Practical Manifolds

What are the meaning and the scope of the concept of “political”? What are the kind of things that can be qualified as “political” (actions, entities of some sort, institutions, none of the above etc.) and why? What sorts of beings can be said to have “political” leanings or dispositions? And, more than everything, why should phenomenology matter when it comes to such questions? Despite the great prominence of Hannah Arendt’s thought, the contemporary debate is quite often ambiguous when it comes to clarify the explicit relations between political thinking and phenomenology. In this lecture I will try to question how the domain of the political might look like if framed within the context of Husserl’s constitutive phenomenology. This should be done following a twofold strategy: (1) from an historical perspective, our reconstruction of Husserl’s account of the political will be related to and contrasted with some themes and problems raised and formulated in the philosophical tradition. Accordingly, in the first part of the lecture I will extensively discuss some key tenets of Plato’s Republic, Aristotle’s Politics and Aquinas’s Summa Theologiæ. (2) As for the more systematic viewpoint, I will try to show how Husserl’s account of the political—although to some extent quite unrefined and often wanting—leads to what we might ultimately label as a “theory of the constitution of practical manifolds”. Among others, as we will see in the second part of the lecture, such a theory proves itself able to put into question the commonplace distinction between the “social” and the “political”, and rethink the “political subject” independently from the notion of “human condition” or any of its adaptations and variants. Such a twofold strategy should also allow for the critical assessment of some current attempts to develop a “political phenomenology” and/or a “phenomenology of the political”.

Darian Meacham (UWE, Bristol/BrisSynBio)

European Institutions? The European Crisis and The Crisis of the European Sciences

Institution (Stiftung, institution, instauration, établissement) is perhaps the most important political-phenomenological concept. It plays a central role in Husserl’s account of character, intersubjectivity, ideal-cultural objects, history and finally crisis. The Crisis of the European Sciences is ultimately best understood as a crisis of institutions. The concept is picked up by Merleau-Ponty and becomes one of the cornerstones of his later philosophy of history, politics and finally ontology. Merleau-Ponty’s deployment of the concept, together with its counterpart, style, opens up new possibilities for thinking the intertwining of the natural and cultural worlds. Institution has a second life in Sartre’s Critique of Dialectal Reason (1960) and the work of Cornelius Castoriadis (L’Institution imaginaire de la société 1975), work that was influenced by Merleau-Ponty. It also appears in the early work of Gilles Deleuze (Instinct et institutions 1955), contemporaneous with Merleau-Ponty’s course on the concept at the Collège de France (Institution et passivité). This seminar will explore the vicissitudes of the concept in its relevance to the development of a phenomenological political philosophy. We will pay particular attention to how the concept of institution might be relevant to understanding the present European crisis, and to understanding the concept of Europe itself. In addition to the more historical sources mentioned above, the topic will also be parsed through contemporary work that draws together work in embodied cognition and evolutionary theory (Gallagher and Crisafi 2009).

A guide article will be provided to participants ahead of the seminar.

Gian Luigi Paltrinieri (Ca’ Foscari University Venice)

Earth, Soil, Territory. How could Martin Heidegger, Interpreter of Phenomenology, become a Nazi?

In Being and Time, his main work (1927), Heidegger describes Human existence and not the German Man, shedding light upon an intrinsically impure being in contrast with any purist and worldless hypostasis. More than this: in Being and Time Heidegger insists upon the constitutive openness on which we depend in that we exist. We are Being-in-the-world, that properly means that the world is not our private house nor something identifiable with a nationalistic homeland. How could then Heidegger – only six years later – become a Nazi? Did he confuse earth with soil, and soil with territory? How could he identify the world with a provincial context in a localistic sense? After denouncing as inauthentic any borrowing and copying stereotypes from the public dimension of Chatter, is Heidegger being held hostage by the most trivial anti-Semitic prejudices? What relationship can link a great thinker to a tyrannical power?

In his Black Notebooks Heidegger claims that the Jewish question (Judenfrage) is “only” a metaphysical question, not a racial one, yet he adds that it does involve a specific kind of humanity, from which Europe has to liberate itself. What could putting in question a calculating and rootless way of thinking have to do with the annihilation of the Jewish people? Has Heidegger simply replaced the bright drive of Husserlian philosophy as a rigorous science, the force of truth, with the truth of force?

Emiliano Trizio (Seattle University)

On Klaus Held’s Phenomenology of the Political World

In this seminar, I will present and, subsequently, discuss the essential traits of the “phenomenology of the political world” recently developed by the German philosopher Klaus Held in the book Phänomenologie der politischen Welt (2010) and in a number of other publications. Held’s starting point lies in the conviction that phenomenology can contribute to the study of the political only if its central theme, which according to Husserl consisted in consciousness, and, according to Heidegger, in being, is identified, instead, with the world. Thus, in light of this approach, the thematization of the political has far-reaching consequences for the theoretical development of phenomenology itself. Indeed, Held’s analysis focuses on the Greek origins of both democracy and philosophy, and leads to thesis that a thematization of the political world constitutes a necessary component of the way phenomenology reconstructs the overcoming of the doxastic relation to the world called “natural attitude” and the resulting institution of the idea of a philosophical episteme. Thus, according to this perspective, a phenomenology of the political world is also required for a correct self-understanding of phenomenology itself.